In 2011, the philosopher Jerry Fodor riled up philosophers and scientists alike with the release of a book, co-written with a cognitive psychologist, criticizing Darwin and his theory of natural selection (Fodor and Piattelli-Palmarini 2011). Fodor is a card-carrying atheist, and accepts most of what modern evolutionary biology teaches: the glaring exception being the theory of natural selection. If I read Fodor correctly, this is roughly what he argues in his book, “What Darwin got wrong”: The theory of natural selection is—by itself—empty or unexplanatory. This is because, for any two linked traits (e.g. pumping blood and thump thump noises), the theory does not tell you which was selected for. In the case of the heart, evolutionary biologists know perfectly damn well that it was selected for pumping blood (Fodor thinks even his grandma could have known that!). However, the evolutionary biologists are drawing from lots of empirical evidence and fields of study (e.g. functional biology) that fall outside the reach of the theory of natural selection. Since Darwin’s theory does not provide an answer to the selection question (i.e. pump or thump?), natural selection—understood as a scientific theory—does not account for the very phenomenon it tries to explain (i.e. the selection of traits). Fodor thinks that trying to provide a selection mechanism to save the theory is a fool’s errand, since there’s likely no such mechanism. Therefore, Fodor concludes that we should give up on the theory all together. There are two burning questions: 1) how does Fodor reach this conclusion? & 2) what is the significance of Fodor’s claim (if he’s right)?
§1: The theory of natural selection
Before I get to Fodor, I will quickly summarize
some basic concepts with the aim of further illuminating Darwin’s theory. Those
who are familiar with the theory can skip or skim most of this section.
Darwin’s theory is predicated on two theses: 1) common descent and 2) the
transmutation of species. Roughly, these state that 1) all life on earth shared
a common ancestor (in the distant past) and 2) lifeforms have changed—or
evolved—over time. The second thesis can be equated with evolution, understood
as a natural phenomenon. The theory of natural selection aims to explain how
evolution is possible. Amongst laypeople, it is commonly asked whether or not
evolution is true, or whether the theory of evolution has been proven. However,
both of these questions are ill-posed.
I think that the question of whether evolution
is true or not commits, what philosophers call, a category mistake. If one
understands evolution to be the mere phenomenon of creatures changing or
evolving over time, then such a question would be akin to “Is gravity, or
precipitation true?” Gravity is a natural phenomenon, one we are all familiar
with. In addition, there are theories of gravity (e.g. Einstein’s general
relativity theory) that explain how the phenomenon works. It would be strange
to say that gravity—the phenomenon itself—is true. Likewise, it is improper to
say that evolution is true. Phenomena cannot be true or false; they just occur
or not and can observed or detected. The main disconnect between gravity and
evolution is that virtually all of us directly observe the former but not the
latter. Evolution—like other natural phenomena (e.g. formation of islands,
glacial movements)—is typically too slow or subtle for most of us to notice in
the real world. However, scientists observe evolution occurring (both directly
and indirectly) on a regular basis (e.g. the evolution of the flu virus).
Taking up the second question—of provability—is
again making a category mistake. There are no instances of proven scientific
theories because they aren’t the sorts of things that can be proved. It would
be like asking, “What is the marital status of a triangle?” Proofs are perhaps
the standard in disciplines like mathematics, but not in science. Scientific
theories perform a number of functions. Explanation is perhaps the most
important role. Of explanations, we can ask whether or not they are adequate, plausible,
well supported by evidence and so on. It is often remarked that “evolution is
just a theory”. But this ignores the wide spectrum of theories, some of which
aren’t supported at all by evidence (e.g. Dogs are cleverly disguised
Martians), and our scientific theories supported by an overwhelming amount of
evidence (e.g. relativity theory, quantum mechanics, plate tectonics). It would
be like saying that “So and so is just a basketball player”, discounting all of
the diversity of skill level that could fall under such a description. No
reasonable person would lump their next door neighbor, who plays basketball for
fun by himself on weekends, to an NBA hall of famer. Likewise, no reasonable
person should put well-supported scientific theories into the same boat with
wildly speculative and empirically unsupported theories.
The theory of natural selection is typically
broken down into three key ideas that aim to explain how species evolve over
time: variation, inheritance and selection. The first two ideas are fairly
straightforward. First, in order for creatures to change over time, there needs
to be some way for differences (e.g. anatomical) between creatures to accrue.
An organism that gave birth to a carbon copy of itself would result in no
species change. Second, mere trait changes would not get very far if there
wasn’t a way for the offspring to inherit those changes. We now know that both
variation and inheritance can be explained at the level of the gene, and that
genes can be altered through random mutations which result from a number of
causes (e.g. UV rays, natural sources of radiation on Earth, genetic copying
mishaps). Genetic variation combined with a mechanism of inheritance (i.e.
genes) provides a way for creatures to change over time.
The final piece of the puzzle is to account for
why certain creatures survive and pass along their genes, while others die out.
Darwin made a distinction between two kinds of solutions. The creatures can be
selected (to survive) either artificially or naturally. Artificial selection is
perhaps best exemplified by the evolution of the domestic dog. All domestic
dogs—including the Chihuahua and Great Dane—shared a common wolf ancestor
roughly 30,000 years ago (Skoglund 2015). Modern domestic dogs vary so significantly
because of humans, whom artificially selected the nicest and prettiest wolves.
Natural selection involves no selecting agents such as humans. Natural
selection occurs by a number of means, though natural disasters (e.g. forest
fires, tsunamis), disease, and predators are the big three. Typically, the
creatures that survive long enough to reproduce are the ones that are best
adapted to their environment. Sadly, since most environments change over time
(e.g. due to climate change, asteroid impacts, etc.), most creatures will die
out. Roughly 98% of all creatures that have ever existed have gone extinct. The
survivors—including us humans—did not just get lucky; all extant life on the
planet survived for a reason, namely, we all more-or-less inherited the traits
necessary to survive in our respective environments.
§2: How Fodor gets there
The previous section laid out Darwin’s theory of
natural selection in a nutshell. To make the issues more engaging, one might
now imagine Fodor’s reaction after sitting in on such an overview of the
theory.
Fodor: Artificial selection makes a lot of
sense; it’s the natural selection part that gets me. When a dog breeder selects
the dogs he wishes to breed, there is both an obvious selection mechanism at
work (i.e the dog breeder) and an obvious way to determine which trait is being
selected for; you just ask the guy! However, when it comes to natural
selection, there is the question, for any pair of linked traits (e.g. pumping
blood and thump thump noises), which gets selected for? There is first the
issue of there being no human breeder (e.g. God) to interrogate, as well as the
issue of what a natural selection mechanism—that picks out one trait and not
the other—would even look like. In every instance where you have linked traits,
it seems as if ‘nature’ has to select both. It is obvious to everyone that
there is a fact of the matter about which trait is being selected for (the
heart!), but there doesn’t seem to be a way for Darwin’s theory to tell us
which, absent some kind of natural selection mechanism or a law of adaptation.
Upon learning about evolutionary theory, really
no one (other than Fodor) raises such problems. Why is the theory so
commonsensical to scientists and laypeople alike, but so incoherent to Fodor? I
think there is a straightforward answer, and one that does not appeal to
name-calling. Fodor has some pretty sophisticated views about the nature of
scientific theories, laws and explanations. The reason why scientists don’t
really engage with his claims is because they probably don’t have any
well-developed views on the nature of explanation and science, both of which
typically fall under the heading of ‘philosophy of science.’ The reason why
most philosophers of science have not “seen the light” is because Fodor’s views
on these matters are not widely held today. For example, Fodor endorses
Hempel’s deductive-nomological (DN) model of explanation (Smith 2008). Without
getting into the details, this view on explanation does not work very well for
Darwin’s theory, an observation made well before the publication of Fodor’s
book (Hempel 1965). For those uninterested in evaluating the merits of the
competing philosophical views on explanation, here is an (overly simplistic) argument
you might find helpful.
What Fodor says about natural selection
essentially hinges on the truth of Hempel’s view on explanation. If Hempel’s
view is wrong, then Fodor is wrong. According to most contemporary philosophers
of science, it is doubtful that Hempel’s view works (see Strevens 2006 for an
overview). Therefore, Fodor is (probably) wrong about Darwin’s theory.
§3. What if Fodor’s right?
Given that Fodor concedes that evolutionary
biologists have the tools answer the selection question, the science can
proceed as it has for some time. However, I think that the scientists would
have to concede that they aren’t answering the selection question via the
theory of natural selection. Additionally, they would have to admit that the
theory of natural selection adds nothing to their scientific understanding of
selection effects. What would then become of the theory? One might think that
the theory might still be perfectly useful as a metaphor for introductory
purposes. Perhaps eventually, an even better metaphor might replace Darwin’s
own (Fodor and Piattelli-Palmarini 2011, ch. 9). However, one might still be
unimpressed with Fodor’s argument. So what if we don’t derive truths about
selection effects from Darwin’s theory? Darwin laid the groundwork for fields
that now do manage to get at those truths. If all that we have to change is how
we should talk about Darwin’s theory, no one is really going to care. But I
believe Fodor’s claim (if right) would actually be somewhat significant. You
wouldn’t be able to call Darwin’s theory a theory any longer. Would this cause
celebration amongst creationist circles, or some embarrassment amongst
evolutionary biologists? Possibly so. Would it change anything about how the
actual science proceeds? Probably not.
Works cited
Darwin, C. (1897). The origin of species by
means of natural selection, or, The preservation of favored races in the
struggle for life. Vol. 1. International Science Library.
Fodor, J., & Piattelli-Palmarini, M. (2011).
What Darwin got wrong. Profile books. Chicago
Godfrey-smith, Peter (2008). Explanation in
evolutionary biology: Comments on Fodor. Mind and Language 23 (1):32–41.
Hempel, Carl (1965). Aspects of Scientific
Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. The Free Press.
Neander, Karen (1991). Functions as selected
effects: The conceptual analyst's defense. Philosophy of Science 58
(2):168-184.
Skoglund, P. (2015). "Ancient wolf genome
reveals an early divergence of domestic dog ancestors and admixture into
high-latitude breeds". Current Biology 25 (11): 1515–9.
Strevens, M. (2006). Scientific explanation.
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, second edition. DM Borchert (ed.). Detroit:
Macmillan Reference USA.