When a banana
harvesting machine detects and grabs a banana, there is nothing it’s like to be
that machine. The machine does not have a point of view or a stream of
consciousness. But when a human or monkey looks a banana, there is something
it’s like for us to see it. Qualities of the fruit’s shape, size, and color
manifest in our stream of consciousness. If we grasp the object, we can feel
its texture and firmness. And if we bite into the banana, we can taste its sweetness.
Most agree that primates are not the only kinds of creatures that have
experiences like taste, smell, sight, touch, sounds, pleasure and pain. But it
can be difficult to sort out which other creatures do, as well as the qualities
that decorate their inner worlds. Do worms have any experiences or are they
like the banana harvesting machine? Do wasps experience pain when sprayed with
Raid? Do fish experience fear or sadness? And what should we say about
octopuses?
You might ask, “how
we could possibly know what’s going on inside another creature’s head?!” There’s
no way to peek inside to see their thoughts or emotions. What if all nonhuman
creatures are mindless machines? The 17th century philosopher Rene
Descartes thought that animals were complex automata that God designed for us
to use, programmed to react to stimuli without ever feeling or thinking
anything. Humans are special, says Descartes, because we are immaterial souls
created by God to exercise free control over our bodies. While we can’t definitively
say he is wrong, Descartes’s views about animal minds are now extremely controversial,
even among theists. But why exactly do most philosophers today reject Descartes’s
views about animals? Part of the story is that we’ve learned a lot more about
animal behavior, the brain, and the evolution of life on Earth. The other part
of the story involves reasoning from this newly acquired knowledge to the
existence of animal minds. Conceptual tools like analogical inferences and
inferences to the best explanation can be used to build bridges between our observations
of the world and our theories. Before judging the reasons philosophers have for
thinking some animals have minds, it’s useful to first review the reasons for
thinking that other people have minds.
How do you know
that you aren’t alone in this world? It’s possible that all other humans that
you interact with are like the banana harvesting machine but behave like they
have minds. How could that be? Perhaps you are in a perfect computer simulation
and those around you are all mindless NPCs. Or maybe your mind has just been
spontaneously created by a freak natural accident with false memories of a past
and you’re currently dreaming all of this up. It’s impossible to conclusively disprove
either of these scenarios using observations, however unlikely we take them to
be. Any form of evidence against either hypothesis could be understood as part
of a well-designed simulation or a vivid dream. So, if we’re going to discount
the possibility of knowing about other nonhuman minds, on the grounds that it’s
possible Descartes is right, we must also say the same about the minds of our
family and friends. I don’t think we need to conclusively rule out these
radical skeptical scenarios to justifiably believe there are other minds. But what
then justifies our beliefs about other minds?
There are many similarities
that I can observe between me and other humans. Typically, other humans make
eye contact during conversation and can infer the kind of mood I’m in. They can
answer questions about what’s on their mind, they scream when they stub their toes
and sometimes will laugh at my jokes. They also have similar brains and perceptual
organs to my own, not created by a mad scientist, but are products of evolution by natural
selection. If other humans behave in consistently similar ways to me across a
wide range of contexts, are neurobiologically very similar, and have an
evolutionary history, then they (probably) have a mind like I do. The inference
from my own mind to other humans is not airtight, but it’s the nearly as strong
as can be. The only stronger inference to other minds would involve my perfect clone.
Applying this inference
to creatures outside our species gets trickier. Nonhumans often exhibit
different behaviors, vary in their neuroanatomy, and have different
evolutionary histories. But still, the inference remains very strong for at least
some groupings of creatures. Nonhuman apes like chimpanzees exhibit many of the
same behaviors as us, have a complex brain with a neocortex, and they are
evolutionarily closely related to us. The common ancestor between chimpanzees
and humans can be traced back to around six million years ago, which in
evolutionary time is not very long ago. Chimpanzees exhibit complex and flexible
behaviors that are best explained by the presence of psychological capacities
such as self-awareness, episodic memory and foresight, as well as logical and
mathematical reasoning. If we can be at least 99% sure other humans have minds,
we can be at least 98% sure chimpanzees do too.
The common
ancestor of all mammals lived around 180 million years ago. The timescale is grand
enough for some mammals to have evolved significantly different behavioral and
neuroanatomical traits, but no such examples have (yet) been discovered. All
mammals have the same basic structure including the possession of a neocortex found
in us and chimpanzees. So, generalizing this analogical inference to all
mammals is also well justified.
When around other mammals,
many just find it obvious that they have minds like we do. It’s especially true
when considering cats and dogs. We often attribute a wide range of mental
states to them without much deliberation. Most people who attribute mental
states to their pets don’t know much about the brain or evolutionary theory but
clearly recognize the many behavioral similarities between us and them. Certain
observed behaviors cry out for an explanation and the possession of a mind
seems like the best one. When a cat screams after its owner steps on its tail,
we infer that the cat is in pain. When a cat meows after long periods without
food, we infer that they are hungry. And when a cat runs away from helium
balloons or cucumbers, we infer that they saw the object and are afraid of it.
As a cat owner, I could spend all day listing examples.
We, in principle,
could learn something about cats, chimpanzees, or other humans that casts
serious doubt upon the existence of their minds. We could in the process of
doing brain surgery, we discover that other humans have hard drives in their
skulls. Or maybe we are approached by men in black suits who provide ample
evidence that this world is a computer simulation. Perhaps Descartes is right about
animals and God informs us through an act of revelation. But merely imagining
ways that others may not have minds, given all the evidence to the contrary, does
not create a reasonable doubt.
In surveying other groupings of animals, we’ll encounter some potentially relevant differences. As we will see, it is more difficult to justifiably infer the existence of animal consciousness outside of our mammalian class, and in some cases, it will make sense to deny mentality to some of these other groupings. In the next post of this series, I will evaluate the prospects for four non-mammalian animal groupings: annelids, bivalves, cnidarians, and gastropods. Do earthworms feel pain when hooked? Can clams feel the steam rising from a cooking pan? Is there something it’s like for jellyfish see or smell bioluminescence? Do sea slugs fear their predators?