“Non-Religious Ethics is at a very early stage. We cannot yet predict whether, as in Mathematics, we will all reach agreement. Since we cannot know how Ethics will develop, it is not irrational to have high hopes”. Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons, 1984
Ethical theories aim to explain why
certain actions are right or wrong. They also aim to
inform us of how we ought to make ethical decisions. Instead of approaching the
subject of ethics by reflecting upon some abstract set of principles, some just
appeal the moral authority of holy books or directly to the God those books
were inspired by. Some would even consider the appeal to holy books to be an
ethical theory of its own (i.e. divine command theory). Religious
texts may offer moral wisdom and sound ethical principles to live by, but
philosophers have been developing ethical theories—without appealing to God—for
over two thousand years. Out of all of the theoretical options, is it
reasonable to think that one ethical theory should be preferred? That is to
say, is there an ethical theory that is objectively true, rendering all other
theories false? There are several reasons for skepticism.
First, there are some who think that
without God, morality has no foundation (*This problem arises particularly for
philosophers because most are nonbelievers). The
idea is that without some kind of objective standard of right and
wrong—independent of anyone’s opinion—morality lacks a proper basis. Without
an independent basis for morality, nothing is really right or wrong.There
is much to say about this, but I will only raise two quick related objections.
First, depending on how one understands the independence requirement,
mathematical, logical, and scientific truths may also lack an “objective”
basis. If morality has an objective foundation, it will be like mathematics or
logic, starting from rationally intuitive, or self-evidently true starting
axioms. Furthermore, on this reading of objectivity, even the existence of God
might not be sufficient for objective morality. To cover some of the same
ground as the old Euthyphro dillema, what makes
the standards that God commands objective? Is it that since he is all knowing,
he can perform all of the necessary moral calculations to determine what is
right and wrong? Is it that the mind of God such that no moral calculations are
necessary, and that God just automatically knows what is right and wrong via
some inner moral sense that is perfect? Objectivity can be understood in weaker
terms. Just like Descartes has been criticized for his defense of a strong conception of knowledge (i.e. requiring absolute certainty),
we can criticize certain philosophers (e.g. William Lane Craig) for proposing
a conception of objectivity that is too strong.
Second, there exists lots of
disagreement about morality. The existence of moral disagreement across different cultures and
individuals convinces many that moral relativism follows and that there just
aren’t any objective moral truths to discover. The fact that there is moral
disagreement does not refute objectivism, as it could be the case that most
people are bad at moral reasoning or are ignorant of the relevant facts. Just
as in the case of when you find people disagreeing on Facebook about the answer
to a mathematical equation, doesn’t show that there isn’t a right solution,
people disagreeing about the answer to a moral question doesn’t show there
isn’t a right one. Some people are just bad at reasoning or ignorant of the
facts relevant to solving a given problem. However, disagreement that
obtains when two parties agree on all of the relevant facts, and employ sound
logical reasoning, does seem problematic for objectivism. Persistent moral disagreement is not just thought to be theoretical,
but actual, amongst experts in moral philosophy. To be clear, the presence of
moral agreement is not required for objectivism to be true. It is not as if
moral claims are made true by virtue of a consensus. That would
be a really weird metaphysical view. The idea is that a consensus amongst
experts would strongly suggest that there are objective answers
to questions of right and wrong and that its absence suggests the falsity of
objectivism.
The late philosopher Derek Parfit
argued that most moral disagreement amongst experts is illusory. It is often
assumed that the major ethical theories (e.g. utilitarianism, contractualism,
and Kantianism) are incompatible with one another. But Parfit argued that once
the views are properly understood, they actually complement one another and can
be combined into overarching ethical theory he called ‘triple theory’ (1, 2).
Parfit thinks the predicament moral philosophers find themselves in is similar
to those of several hikers climbing different sides of the same mountain. It is
only once the hikers reach the mountain’s summit, that they realize that they
were all climbing the same mountain all along. Parfit’s claims are highly
controversial, but worth taking seriously. For if his claims regarding moral
disagreement are true, then there may be a strong case for moral objectivism.
It may be argued that constraining the
analysis of ethical theories to those espoused by contemporary English speaking
moral philosophers may be unjustified. What about all of the other forms of
moral diversity in the world? For example, Confucianism, Buddhism, Hinduism,
and the views of conservatives in the United States, all offer contrary
accounts of morality than those of contemporary philosophers. The psychologist
Jonathan Haidt, has deconstructed differing systems of morality around the
world into five or six basic values: care, fairness, liberty, loyalty, respect,
and purity (3). Most moral philosophers, and political liberals, tend to view
the first three values as central to moral theorizing, whereas religious
conservatives tend to emphasize the importance of the last three. Haidt’s
theory of moral foundations might show that there exist different starting
points for moral theorizing, and that no one set of starting value assumptions
is more valid than another. Moral pluralism, the view which states that there
are several objectively true moral theories, might find support in Haidt’s work.
A response I find natural is to say that
all of these differing value systems fail to stand up to the standards of
rationality and logic. They appeal to a combination of false religious beliefs,
the cultural practices or prejudices of one’s community, and negative emotional
responses (e.g. disgust), all of which we have good reason to reject. The
ethical theories proposed by philosophers are intended to be as far removed
from prejudice and uninformed opinion as possible. Moral philosophers spend
most of their lives developing objective reasons and arguments for why certain
moral principles are plausible and should be accepted by any rational person.
Since the ethical views espoused by religious believers are, for the most part,
not well-considered, motivated by logical consistency, or backed by rational
arguments, there is reason to suspect their beliefs about morality are
mistaken. It may sound elitist to make such claims, but I think most of us
would agree to the argument’s application with respect to most other domains of
inquiry (e.g. science, mathematics). Scientists are much more likely to be
right about an issue than laypeople who are completely uninformed. Why
shouldn’t the same be true about ethics? To be clear, I do not want to say that
the major religions get everything wrong about morality. I just want to make
the point since their moral teachings were not based upon the same
methodological standards as contemporary moral theories, we have some reason to
doubt that they have equal claim to truth.
A philosopher who, in my view,
pioneered the path for an objective moral theory was the 19th century thinker Henry Sidgwick (4).
Sidgwick defended a sophisticated version of utilitarianism that proved to be
influential to the great moral philosophers of the 20th century (e.g. Parfit) (5). Reflecting
upon the views of Sidgwick and Parfit have led me to seriously reconsider the
merits of objectivism. While I did not flesh out either of their views in this
post, I think there is much to admire about their philosophical projects,
enough to spend several future blog posts discussing and appreciating.
References
References
1) Parfit, D.,
& Scheffler, S. (2011). On
what matters: volume one (Vol. 1). Oxford University Press.
2) Parfit, D., & Scheffler, S. (2011). On what matters: volume two (Vol. 2). Oxford University Press.
3) Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. Vintage.
4) Sidgwick, H. (1907). The methods of ethics. Hackett Publishing.
2) Parfit, D., & Scheffler, S. (2011). On what matters: volume two (Vol. 2). Oxford University Press.
3) Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. Vintage.
4) Sidgwick, H. (1907). The methods of ethics. Hackett Publishing.
5) de
Lazari-Radek, K., & Singer, P. (2014). The
point of view of the universe: Sidgwick and contemporary ethics. OUP
Oxford.
No comments:
Post a Comment